Paragone

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Benedetto Varchi, by Titian

Paragone (Italian: paragone, meaning comparison), was a debate during the Italian Renaissance in which painting and sculpture (and to a degree, architecture) were each championed as forms of art superior and distinct to each other.[1] While other art forms, such as architecture and poetry existed in the context of the debate, painting and sculpture were the primary focus of the debate.[2][3][1]

The debate extended beyond the fifteenth century and even influences the discussion and interpretation of artworks that may or may not have been influenced by the debate itself.[4]

A comparable question, generally posed less competitively, was known as ut pictura poesis (a quote from Horace), comparing the qualities of painting and poetry.[5]

The debate[edit]

The debate began around the 15th century.[4] Leonardo da Vinci's treatise on painting, observing the difficulty of painting and supremacy of sight, is a notable example of literature on the subject.

Bendetto Varchi further sparked the conversation between artists in 1546 by sending out letters inviting opinions.[2][6] Painters and sculptors each vied for their respective side in the debate.[6] Michelangelo was the only artist who offered support for both mediums.[6] However, he was also found to be less invested in the discussion despite his contributions.[3]

The essence of the debate had many facets. Comparisons of the two mediums ranged from conceptual themes to practices, underscoring the intellectual role of the artist in the era.[6]

Geralamo Salvado's Gaston de la Foix

Each medium had multiple points in support of it. Much of the debate lacked specific examples of supporting work, though the ideas were extensively discussed.[6] Giorgio Vasari argued that drawing is the father of all arts, and as such, the most important one.[7] Sculpture was typically claimed to be the only method of having several different and faithful views of the same figure by those who found it to be the more superior medium.[6] A counterpoint to this argument was made in paintings which feature reflective objects or surfaces, such as the Portrait of Gaston de la Foix by Gerolamo Savoldo, which featured mirrors surrounding the key figure.[6] This allowed figures not only to be viewed at multiple angles, but for these to be seen at the same time, which is an ability that sculpture is incapable of providing. Many paintings with this concept are brought into the discussion of paragone, but it is unclear how many were actually made as a response to the debate itself.[4]

A large portion of the discussion was centered on the idea of imitation of the natural world.[3] Painting was seen to create an inferior imitation because it lacked form.[6] This argument was later championed by the example of a blind man experiencing art. Theoretically, he could gather how a sculpture was structured through touch, but were he to touch a painting he would not be able to construct an image of the work, thus rendering painting an illusionary form of art.[6]

Another side of the debate that arose is one of technical skill. Michelangelo did not take a clear side in the debates, but did underscore a component which he believed to be essential to both painting and sculpture, called disegno.[3] Disegno in Renaissance times largely referred to "the conception of a work."[8] The understanding and use of the term was also, however, influenced by the idea of drawing as the foundation of art.[8] Vasari and with him Benvenuto Cellini, also asserted that the ability to render an accurate contour line were technical skills that benefited both painting and sculpture.[3]

Notable contributors[edit]

Many notable artists and other public figures during the fifteenth century and onward contributed to the discussion of paragone, such as:

References[edit]

  1. ^ a b A., Bailey, Gauvin (2012-08-20). Baroque and Rococo. London. p. 9. ISBN 9780714857428. OCLC 804911527.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  2. ^ a b c d "Paragone ('comparison') | Thames & Hudson Dictionary of the Italian Renaissance, The – Credo Reference". search.credoreference.com. Retrieved 2019-02-27.
  3. ^ a b c d e f g Dundas, Judith (1990). "The Paragone and the Art of Michelangelo". Sixteenth Century Journal. 21 (1): 87–92. doi:10.2307/2541134. ISSN 0361-0160. JSTOR 2541134.
  4. ^ a b c Land, Norman (October 1999). "Giovanni Bellini, Jan van Eyck, and the "paragone" of Painting and Sculpture". Source: Notes in the History of Art. 19 (1): 1–8. doi:10.1086/sou.19.1.23206710. ISSN 0737-4453. S2CID 191389078.
  5. ^ "Home". This is Paragon. Retrieved 2019-11-26.
  6. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Hecht, Peter (1984). "The paragone Debate: Ten Illustrations and a Comment". Simiolus: Netherlands Quarterly for the History of Art. 14 (2): 125–136. doi:10.2307/3780590. ISSN 0037-5411. JSTOR 3780590.
  7. ^ a b Vasari, Giorgio (1550). Lives of the Most Excellent Painters, Sculptors, and Architects.
  8. ^ a b "disegno (Italian 'design, drawing') | The Thames & Hudson Dictionary of Art Terms – Credo Reference". search.credoreference.com. Retrieved 2019-04-09.
Secondary sources

External links[edit]